Tuesday, December 10, 2013

WWSD What Would Socrates Do?


What follows was my presentation given at the 2013 Fall Academic Awards at Western Reserve Academy.
 
Not too long ago, a former student of mine introduced me to a prestigious professor of neuroscience at an even more prestigious university.  In the course of our exchange he learned that I was a teacher of Latin, and a sometime teacher of philosophy and ancient Greek.  This professor, quite tactlessly, if you ask me, proceeded to express his surprise that schools continued to offer such subjects and that, worse yet, students enrolled in them of their own volition.  Partly in self-defense, and partly from genuine interest, I asked him to elaborate.  To which he replied, “In my estimation, the Humanities are a moribund and obsolete area of study.All the achievements of mankind are fully explicable in terms of, and are therefore reducible to, neurochemical activity.  It is consequently pointless to investigate such achievements any further, let alone celebrate or marvel at them."

To say the least, I found his remarks unsettling, not so much because of their implication in regards to my personal job security (though I must confess that thought did cross my mind), but rather because of what they intimated about the path down which we, as a culture, are headed.  Now, granted, this professor’s views are extreme; then again, it is nevertheless likely that they are illustrative of a general trend in higher education, particularly in light of how far liberal studies have fallen out of favor in recent years.  And so I thought, “This is getting out of hand; I must do everything in my admittedly quite limited power to stem the tide of such gargantuan stupidity.”  And here I stand before you.  

Oftentimes when I am faced with an intellectual dilemma, I turn to that most inveterate of all questioners, my patron saint, as it were, Socrates.  I wonder what Socrates would say about all this.  Curiously enough, he was born into a predicament very like our own.
The Death of Socrates, Jean-Louis David
There he is, the paradigmatic philosopher himself.  As much as I love this painting, however, it misrepresents Socrates in two important respects.  First of all, there’s no way Socrates was that buff; he spent his days badgering people, not pumping iron.
This is in all likelihood the more accurate representation.


Second, his hand gesture, index finger pointing heavenward, suggesting that soon after he drinks the contents of the profferred goblet, that’s where he will go, belies one of the most fundamental – if not THE most fundamental – of his teachings.  You see, Socrates is distinct among philosophers of the Western world in that he never once made a positive claim about the nature of reality or the human condition.  He spent all of his time investigating, asking the big questions, if you like, and although he unmasked many a pretension to wisdom among his fellow Athenians – that was, in fact, why they executed him, for being an indefatigable pain in the butt – he never himself provided answers to those questions.  Indeed, he saw it as his gods-given mission to upset the stagnant complacency of those with whom he came into contact every day, to be, as he himself articulated his role, the buzzing, biting, and relentlessly annoying gadfly to Athens’ steed.  This explains at one and the same time why the elder citizens of Athens by and large hated him, and why the young adored him.  Socrates had a unique talent for making pompous men look like idiots, and young people universally relish the humiliation of their elders.  And while many believed Socrates had the answers to the questions he was asking, the fact is, he didn’t.  For this reason, to represent Socrates as convinced of the immortality of his soul misses the mark.  In his defense-speech, in fact, he said to those who would have had him acquitted, that to fear death is to construe it as an evil and therefore to pretend to know what one cannot know.  It may well be that upon death the soul will transmigrate; but it’s every bit as likely, he urged, that death is a complete cessation of consciousness, that we flicker out of existence in the manner of a candle’s flame.  We’ll just have to wait and see, or, not see, as the case may be.


But in what way or ways was the situation in Socrates’ day akin to our own?  Socrates’ cleverest and most formidable opponents were the Sophists.


He seems to have objected to them on three counts.  First, the very name, Sophists, which in Greek simply means “wise ones,” made them a manifest target for Socratic dialectic.  Second, they appear one and all to have adopted a relativistic understanding of truth.  Relativism – not to be confused with relativity – is the conviction, albeit a highly paradoxical one, that truths are always and everywhere specific to a given culture, or, more radically, a given individual.  Protagoras, for instance, one of the more famous Sophists, was quoted as saying “Man is the measure of things.”


And although it may seem at first blush that Socrates, ever the skeptic, would have found relativism congenial, relativism is, in the end, a logically untenable position, and Socrates was never one to suffer illogic gladly.  After all, the relativist would presumably maintain that the relativity of truth is true, and in this way, relativism is always doomed to undermine itself.  And the third thing Socrates found objectionable about the Sophists was their presumption in claiming that they taught their students arete, another Greek word, which can be translated rather loosely to mean “virtue” or “excellence.”  The Sophists presumed to be teaching their students how to be excellent human beings.  But above all what they really taught was rhetoric, the art of speaking persuasively, a practice that was at least consistent with their relativism.  At the end of the day, nobody knows what it means to be an excellent human being, least of all the Sophists, who really just taught their students how to achieve wealth, power, and prestige – none of which connects, even remotely, with human excellence.  And since the Sophists pretended to know and care about the education of the young, arguably the most important endeavor of all, their offense was especially egregious.
So, if we take a comparative look at our own day, we see on a larger scale much the same predicament as that of Athens in the 5th century B.C.  (Actually, I would contend we’re quite a bit worse off than the Athenians, but that’s a topic for another speech.)  Our education becomes more and more vocational with each passing decade, if not each year, presumably because we have deemed the purpose of education one of teaching the young how to go about acquiring the greatest share possible of money and influence.  And most of us in this day and age take relativism for granted, although our relativism is even sillier than that of the Sophists, since it’s motivated by the absolute value of tolerance.  That is to say, we mistake multiculturalism for relativism, somehow overlooking the obvious contradiction in our belief that it is wrong – absolutely wrong – to judge one culture superior to another.

And what of the Sophists themselves?  Where shall we find our latter-day Sophists?  They’re all over the place, actually, but at the moment some of their most vociferous incarnations are the popular scientists, folks like Richard Dawkins and Daniel Dennett, folks like our socially inept professor of neuroscience.  Some dismiss the Humanities as obsolete, but others, recognizing that the questions traditionally raised and addressed by the Humanities will never go away, have tried to subsume those questions under the general purview of science.

But there’s a problem here, a big one.  The nineteenth-century German philosopher, Friedrich Nietzsche, once said, “If I have my ‘why’ of life, I can put up with almost any ‘how’.”  He meant to suggest that human beings by their very nature evaluate existence.  What makes us distinctive as a species is the fact that we give meaning to our lives.  Indeed, so inherent is this trait in us that without meaning, we can’t survive.  The meaning is our “‘why’ of life.”  Now, if we look to science for that ‘why,’ we’ll encounter nothing but a resounding silence.  To be sure, science has given us a very convincing ‘how’ of life in the doctrines of Big Bang and evolution.  But it would be utterly futile to look to these doctrines for an answer to the question ‘why.’  In fact, they would seem to rule out the very possibility of a ‘why.’  According to these doctrines, we are merely the product of a cosmic accident, and our level of sophistication is nothing more than the consequence of eons of random mutation and natural selection.  The gold they’re peddling, these pop-scientists, is fools’ gold.
But let me be clear.  I don’t mean to attack the great and important work of science.  What I do contest is the flippant dismissal of the Humanities on the part of an industry, which doesn’t even have the insight to recognize the contradictions embedded in its very core.  That, my friends, is Sophistry of the highest order. 

So, who will be our Socrates, bringing us the hope of redemption?  Well, that’s your job, you intrepid truth-seekers of Western Reserve Academy.
So long as you and the generations that follow you continue to hold aloft that torch, bringing to light the ubiquitous sophistry of our culture, the Humanities will remain a vital, indeed the most vital, part of our education.  You really do have that power, the power to save our souls.

Wednesday, January 9, 2013

Latin and the Love of Wisdom: Why Philosophy Ought to be Incorporated into the Latin Curriculum

When I told my sister-in-law the title of this presentation, she told me that it sounded rather self-serving. Granted, she has never been one to mince her words, but there is nonetheless a good deal of truth in what she said. You see, I began my career in education not as a Latin teacher but as an adjunct professor of philosophy, and while I would like to say that I devoted all of my time in graduate school poring over the works of the classical philosophers, the fact is I was at that time far more interested in Nietzsche, Husserl, Heidegger, and Derrida than I was in Epictetus, Epicurus, Lucretius, Cicero, and Seneca. This is not to say that the latter names were unknown to me; far from it, in fact. I had studied all of them in college, and I even spent a good deal of time reading Lucretius, Cicero, and Seneca in Latin. But I was very young back then, and Nietzsche’s proclamation of the death of God had a much greater appeal to me than did Lucretius’ adaptation of the atomic theory of Democritus. It wasn’t until I started teaching Latin that I took a more careful look at the classical philosophers, especially those who wrote in Latin.

During my first few years as a Latin teacher, introducing my students to works like Lucretius’ De Rerum Natura or Cicero’s Tusculan Disputations or Seneca’s Naturales Quaestiones was a sort of guilty pleasure. A part of me felt that I could be using the time much more wisely, introducing my students to larger portions of the more canonical works. Another part of me recognized, despite my relative inexperience, that there may have been a deeper significance to the fact that I enjoyed teaching the more philosophical works – something beyond my own fascination with philosophy. For not only did I enjoy teaching the philosophical works; my students enjoyed learning about them as well. Of course, one must be careful when assessing a curriculum based upon the pleasure one’s students derive from it; many of my students would be quite content, I think, if we spent four years reading the model sentences and stories at the ends of chapters 1-10 of Jenney’s First Year Latin. That said, I have heard a number of students say that of all the Latin authors they’d read over the course of four years of Latin study their favorite was Lucretius. Now, one might fault Lucretius for many things – his excessive melancholy, his rather lofty attitude, his abundance of neologisms – but I doubt anyone in their right mind would accuse him of being too easy. So why on earth did my students enjoy reading and discussing him? I would even go so far as to say that studying Lucretius and the other Roman philosophers was a guilty pleasure for them as well. It was not at all uncommon for them to plead with me for an “off-day,” by which they meant, not a day of watching Troy or Gladiator but a day of studying philosophy. What was it – what is it – about philosophy in general and Roman philosophy in particular that resonates with them? This I have asked myself for many years, and in what follows I shall attempt to articulate what I believe is the answer.

Let’s begin with philosophy in general. Ever since the time of Socrates, young people have been attracted to philosophy, and while Socrates was perhaps the original “corruptor of the youth,” it seems likely that elders were urging the young people of their communities to ask questions long before he came along. We can chalk this up, partly at least, to youthful iconoclasm – but only partly. It would be hasty and overly facile, I think, to dismiss young people’s enthusiasm for philosophy as nothing more than a will to bring down the hallowed walls of tradition. To return to the figure of Socrates, it is undeniable that a good measure of his seductive power, particularly for the young, lies in his ability to make pompous men look like idiots. At the same time, however, Socrates was no sophist, and although he seldom if ever provided answers to the questions he asked, he was always perfectly clear about why he asked his questions: he always held before him the hope that he was coming ever closer to discovering how it is that human beings ought to live. And the example he thereby set for his students resonated with them to such a degree that we find Plato, his most gifted pupil, naming Socrates - well after his youthful fervor had dissipated - the wisest, most just, and best man he had ever known.

It would seem, then, that the philosopher – and the study that she or he represents – has an appeal for young people that runs deeper than mere intellectual bravado. But what is that deeper appeal?

This is where the Roman philosophers come in. Traditional scholarship maintains that the Romans contributed little or nothing to the enterprise of Western philosophy. After all, the Romans, unlike the Greeks, who created philosophy, were a hard-nosed and pragmatic people; they had no time for lofty metaphysical speculation. One is reminded of that famous passage in Book VI of Vergil’s Aeneid in which the poet speaks of the accomplishments peculiar to the Romans – the very practical accomplishments of war and governance – or of Cato the Censor’s admonition to the Roman people of the potentially corruptive influence of those three philosophical ambassadors who came to Rome from Athens in 155 b.c.e. Whether or not it is true that the Romans made no positive contribution to Western philosophy (I happen to believe that it is not true), it is certainly the case that the Romans were overwhelmed by the cultural achievements of the Greeks, philosophy among them. And while the Romans may well have been practical by temperament, the philosophy of the period in which they rose to eminence in the Mediterranean world – the so-called “silver age” or “Hellenistic” period – was likewise practical. To all the great schools of that period – Stoicism, Epicureanism, etc. – questions of physics and logic, metaphysics and epistemology were considered ancillary to questions of ethics: what is happiness and how does one go about achieving it? Now, without going into a lengthy exploration of the various reasons for this shift away from “ivory tower” philosophy and toward a “philosophy for the people,” it should suffice for our purposes to note that such a shift did occur and that our practical Romans found themselves presented with a philosophy to which they could relate.

But what does all of this have to do with the question of why my students dig the study of philosophy in general and of the Roman philosophers in particular?

At the risk of sounding trite, let’s consider for a moment the kinship between our time and the time in which figures like Lucretius, Cicero, and Seneca; Musonius Rufus, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius were making their ideas known to the people of the Roman world. To begin, we, like Rome, are a superpower, and just as we are at once revered and reviled by the global community, so was Rome. We find ourselves looking back nostalgically to a time when life was simpler and our values more genuine; so did the Romans. We deplore materialism outwardly but inwardly suspect that our lives will improve in proportion to the amount of wealth we acquire; so did the Romans. We have become obsessed with spectacles; so had the Romans. I could go on and on, citing one example after another, but I believe the point has been made. We are the new Rome.

There is one difference, however – an important one. While the Romans could, if they wished, turn to the Hellenistic and Roman philosophers for direction, we have no real contemporary equivalents. Our philosophers have been relegated to the academy, and it would seem that they wouldn’t have it any other way. They divide their time between the careful analysis of language and squabbling over largely inconsequential problems, and woe to the student who looks to them for guidance on life’s most pressing issues. This is not to say, of course, that no one is addressing these issues; talk show hosts, radio personalities, and newspaper columnists grapple with them every day, and I would venture to guess that not a single week passes without the publication of a new self-help book. These latter, and not our contemporary philosophers, are the modern-day’s answer to the Hellenistic and Roman philosophers. The trouble is that there are a great many who find the reflections of these latter-day “philosophers” not just unsatisfying but downright nauseating. Who in their right mind would deliberately send their children to Jerry Springer, Howard Stern, or even Chicken Soup for the Soul in their quest for answers to life’s big questions?

The good news is that by and large “life’s big questions” do not change, and the answers provided by the Hellenistic and Roman philosophers are every bit as relevant today as they were two thousand years ago. I would contend, in fact, that they are more relevant today than they were a hundred or even fifty years ago, given the remarkable likenesses I mentioned between our world and that of the Romans.

Consider, for example, the question, “What is the goal of human life?” When I raise this question for the first time in a class, my students look at me quizzically, clearly wondering what this has to do with Latin. Once I’ve explained to them that language study involves a whole lot more than memorizing forms and vocabulary and requires an engagement with the culture in which a language is (or was) spoken AND that coming to terms with the sorts of questions the Romans asked and with the answers they provided to them is an important part of grasping the cultural backdrop of Latin, they begin to think about the question. Is there a goal to human life? If so, is it the same goal for all human beings? And my students can be remarkably savvy. One might say that life-goals are relative to a given culture, that what we Americans living in the twenty-first century believe to be the goal of human life is not the same as what the ancient Romans believed. Another might consider the question from the point of view of biology and say that the goal of human life is survival, both personal survival and the survival of one’s family and/or species. Here I might point out to them that the Roman philosophers believed, following the lead of Aristotle, that the goal of human life is happiness, and, more often than not, all but the most irascible of students will concede this point: we all want to be happy.

The next question, of course, is, “What is happiness and how do we go about achieving it?” In response to this question, at least half of my students will say that money will make them happy – and who can blame them? They are fed this rubbish every day of their lives. But there’s always one student who raises her hand and says that she knows of at least one person who has a whole lot of money but is nevertheless miserable. Very true! The class agrees. But if money will not make us happy, what will? Fame? No, there are plenty of famous people who are completely wretched. Well, maybe a life full of pleasure and pleasant things will make us happy, another student says. Aha, I say – that is precisely what Lucretius believed. Oh, we like this Lucretius fellow, they say; anyone who believes that the best life is one dedicated to the pursuit of pleasure is OK in our book. Ah, but what is pleasure? Certainly, food and drink can bring us pleasure, but too much food and drink will bring us pain. As it turns out, a life devoted to a maximization of pleasure would necessarily involve a strict moderation – nothing in excess, Horace’s “mediocritas aurea.” And so on and so forth.

What this hypothetical class has shown, I hope, is that the Roman philosophers, introduced into a Latin classroom, can get students thinking about questions they would do very well to ask – especially in this day and age, when the conventional answers are not just hackneyed but downright destructive. More than this, the Roman philosophers will provide them much better guidance in their attempt to formulate their own answers to these questions than most if not all of what is otherwise available to them. Finally, such an introduction will serve to bring the ancient Romans – those who spoke and lived the language they are studying – much closer to them.

And so what I once indulged in as a guilty pleasure has become an integral part of my curriculum, as central as the poetry of Catullus, Horace, and Vergil, the orations of Cicero, the history of Caesar, Livy, and Tacitus, and the letters of Pliny.

Thursday, November 15, 2012

Philosophical Poet or Poetic Philosopher: Lucretius and the Ongoing Quarrel between Philosophy and Poetry

In the early part of the twentieth century the renowned philosopher and Harvard professor, George Santayana, published a wonderful little book entitled Three Philosophical Poets. It is aptly, though perhaps not too inventively, named, as it treats in chronological order three of the more overtly philosophical poets whose magna opera belong to the Western canon: Lucretius, Dante, and Goethe. Santayana’s principal contention in the book is that each one of the three gives voice to a distinct philosophical position or worldview; the work of each poet, that is to say, illustrates his own position’s highest expression. More particularly, he says of Lucretius’s De Rerum Natura that it is the Western world’s loftiest vehicle for NATURALISM, Dante’s Divine Comedy is this same for SUPERNATURALISM, and Goethe’s Faust for ROMANTICISM. These three are, he maintains, the chief phases of European philosophy.

It is an interesting argument, to be sure, and also compelling. But as I read this book and continued to consider its title, I could not help but waver over its implicit argument. These three authors, it seemed to me, exhibited a greater degree of disparity than of kinship. I sensed chiefly that Lucretius and the De Rerum Natura resisted inclusion in this group. Dante and Goethe, I thought, were indeed philosophical poets, but Lucretius would more suitably be classed among the poetic philosophers, in whose company one would find the likes of Empedocles, Parmenides, Plato, Friedrich Nietzsche, Jacques Derrida and others. After all, Lucretius himself claimed that his verse was merely ancillary to his larger purpose – namely, to introduce the salvific doctrines of his master, Epicurus, to the Romans, an audience so clearly and so desperately in need of them. Toward the end of Book I, Lucretius remarks, in a passage that has very justly become famous:

Nunc age, quod super est, cognosce et clarius audi.
nec me animi fallit quam sint obscura; sed acri
percussit thyrso laudis spes magna meum cor
et simul incussit suavem mi in pectus amorem
Musarum, quo nunc instinctus mente vigenti 925
avia Pieridum peragro loca nullius ante
trita solo. iuvat integros accedere fontis
atque haurire iuvatque novos decerpere flores
insignemque meo capiti petere inde coronam,
unde prius nulli velarint tempora Musae; 930
primum quod magnis doceo de rebus et artis
religionum animum nodis exsolvere pergo,
deinde quod obscura de re tam lucida pango
carmina musaeo contingens cuncta lepore.
id quoque enim non ab nulla ratione videtur; 935
sed vel uti pueris absinthia taetra medentes
cum dare conantur, prius oras pocula circum
contingunt mellis dulci flavoque liquore,
ut puerorum aetas inprovida ludificetur
labrorum tenus, interea perpotet amarum 940
absinthi laticem deceptaque non capiatur,
sed potius tali facto recreata valescat,
sic ego nunc, quoniam haec ratio plerumque videtur
tristior esse quibus non est tractata, retroque
volgus abhorret ab hac, volui tibi suaviloquenti 945
carmine Pierio rationem exponere nostram
et quasi musaeo dulci contingere melle,
si tibi forte animum tali ratione tenere
versibus in nostris possem, dum perspicis omnem
naturam rerum, qua constet compta figura. 950

                           De Rerum Natura I.921-950

which I translate as follows:

“Now come, learn and listen more clearly to what remains. It does not escape me how dark these matters are; but the hope of praise has struck my heart with the sharp thyrsus, and at the same time it has struck into my chest the sweet love of the Muses, impelled by which I now wander with vigorous mind through places pathless to the daughters of Pieros, worn away by the foot of none before. It pleases me to approach untouched fountains and drink, and it pleases me to pluck off new flowers and thereupon to seek for my head the illustrious crown, whence the Muses have covered the temples of none before; first, because I teach about great things and proceed to free the soul from the tight bonds of religion, next because I compose verses so clear about an obscure topic, touching all with musical charm. For this too has a function: as with children, when doctors attempt to administer foul wormwood, they first touch the rims around the cups with the sweet, yellow fluidity of honey, so that their unwitting age might be deluded as far as the lips, so that they might drink off the bitter liquid of wormwood and, though deceived, would not be cheated, but rather, restored by such a deed, grow strong. Thus do I now, since this account commonly seems to be rather gloomy to those by whom it has not been considered, and the crowd shrinks back from this doctrine, I have chosen to set forth for you in sweet-speaking Pierian song my account and, as it were, to touch it with the sweet honey of the Muses, if by chance I might be able in my verses to hold your attention with such an account, while you see clearly the nature of things.”

And so it would certainly appear that Lucretius himself conceived the poetic form of the De Rerum Natura as purely incidental. To modernize his simile, the roughly seven thousand and two hundred hexameters were little or no more than the cherry flavoring in Children’s Tylenol. Moreover the motivation behind the passage seems one of justification, as if he were fully expecting some or all of his readers to question or even challenge his chosen medium.

And this brings us to a more profound problem. Indeed, were we to doubt the significance of this passage, this simile, or perhaps miss it the first time round, we could not fail to recognize that it appears again, almost verbatim, as the opening lines of Book IV. Clearly, Lucretius wanted his readers to take note of this simile. But why? Did he have good reason to expect some raised eyebrows over his decision to convey the Epicurean philosophy through the medium of poetry? I believe he in fact had two reasons to believe this, pertaining respectively to Plato on the one hand and to Epicurus himself on the other.

Turning initially to Epicurus, Lucretius’s conception of this philosopher, hailing from what is today commonly referred to as the ‘silver age’ of Greek philosophy, was absolutely unambiguous: he quite literally worshiped him. Not only do the first, third, fifth and sixth books of the De Rerum Natura contain, either at or very near their beginnings, eulogies to him, but also within these eulogies he names him either “divus homo” or, more bluntly, “deus ille.” One would guess that for Lucretius Epicurus was the closest thing to those almost hopelessly contrived, Martian-like deities, who were said to dwell within the intermundia or ‘spaces between the worlds’ and who served for Epicurus and his followers as models of excellence and exemplars of the highest good: perfect tranquility. The trouble was that this ‘god-like’ man, it would seem, did not dig poetry. In his indispensable text, The Lives of the Eminent Philosophers, Diogenes Laertius wrote in reference to the Epicurean sage that “he would not compose poems assiduously.” (10.117-21b) Now, the degree of importance we would attach to the adverb ‘assiduously’ is beside the point; the fact remains that Epicurus evidently urged his disciples to approach the composition of poetry tentatively or, even better, not at all. So, one might well wonder why Lucretius should choose to lay out the central doctrines of Epicureanism in seven-plus thousand lines of beautifully crafted and hard-won lines of dactylic hexameter.

But what was the rationale behind Epicurus’s patent, albeit slightly qualified, prohibition of the poet’s artistry? It appears to have been twofold: first of all, most poetry, and certainly the poetry that is most universally loved and admired, like that, say, of Homer, Hesiod, and company, is positively riddled with lies; indeed, Hesiod’s own Muses admit as much when they inform him that while they surely have the capacity to deliver unto him the truth, they also know how, when they are of a mind, to tell him lies so persuasive that he would have no means of adjudicating the difference between the two. Secondly, poetry, both reading that of others and composing one’s own, is an enterprise so resplendent with passion, with love – also a big no-no in the eyes of the master – that it presents too great a risk of disturbing one’s ataraxia or, to use Lucretius’s term, ‘tranquillitas’. And this brings us to Plato.

In the midst of their theoretical construction of the ideal polis in the Republic, Socrates and his interlocutors eventually confront the problem of education. In the end, they decide, though it pains them all, and not least of all Socrates, to do so, that poetry, replete with lies as it is, would ultimately cause greater harm than good, and so must be banished from the perfectly balanced and therefore perfectly just state.

And yet we cannot help but feel that Socrates, himself Plato’s own artistic rendering of the man, kept his fingers crossed while uttering this pronouncement. For not only must Plato have had some cognizance of the generally poetic character of his dialogues, we also find him, when faced with an especially intractable concept, resorting to metaphor, a tool of the poet, not the philosopher. Thus has he given us his twin-horsed chariot, his ladder of love, his myth of Er, and his allegory of the cave, to name just a few of the more noteworthy examples. Plato’s condemnation of poetry is undermined by the very form in which it is pronounce.

And do we not feel that the same might well be true of Lucretius, that is to say, that his work as a whole, and the simile of the honey-rimmed cup in particular, possesses the same self-refuting character? That simile, as well as the haunting beauty one encounters at almost every turn in the De Rerum Natura, is not reducible to mere supplement. Memos and shopping lists are supplemental; the De Rerum Natura is high art, and as an achievement, it simply would not have been possible without an enormous share of passion, or love.

So it seems Santayana has been vindicated: Lucretius was indeed, and perhaps even despite himself, more the philosophical poet than the poetic philosopher. And we thank our lucky stars.

Monday, April 30, 2012

“When Am I Ever Going to Use This?” And The Problem of Cognitive Diarrhea


As perhaps stands to reason, I’m asked this question more often than most. After all, I teach two subjects here at WRA, the one a reputedly “dead” language, the other a discipline some wit once referred to as “the most interesting path to poverty.” Indeed, a few years ago one of the students in my philosophy class remarked, “So, Mr. Namiotka, it would appear you teach not one but two entirely useless subjects.”  Ouch!  By virtue of my status as “purveyor of the useless,” therefore, I’m uniquely suited to (or at least I have a most vested interest in) answering this classic rhetorical question, a question that stands, for good or ill, as an increasingly compelling objection to the value of liberal arts education in general.

Back in my undergraduate days, I took a course in Ethics. On the very first day, the professor entered the room, put his books down on the desk, and said, “This is the most useless class you will ever take.”  How’s that for a hook? He certainly had our attention. After giving us a moment to take in what he had just said, he continued, “It’s also the most important class you will ever take.”  I don’t recall exactly what I thought upon hearing this, although I imagine I found it appropriately paradoxical, coming as it did from a philosophy professor.  What I do know is that it took me some time to sort out the distinction he was evidently making between what is useful on the one hand, and what is important on the other. Aren’t the two concepts more or less synonymous?

Maybe not. Perhaps the reason that the question – When am I ever going to use this? – is such a familiar one is simply that there is little or nothing that one learns in high school for which one will find a direct application – or use. I like to tell my Latin students that they’ll be very grateful of my services one day when they are confronted in some dark alley by a crazed gunman giving them the choice between death and declining puella. All joking aside, however, the fact is that no matter how beneficial a background in Latin might be for those pursuing careers in medicine or law, no matter how well students of Latin traditionally perform on the verbal section of the SAT, the reason to study Latin – or philosophy or just about any subject one might encounter at the high school level – is not its practical or utilitarian yield.

Now, please don’t misunderstand me: I am certainly not suggesting that no benefits accrue from the study of Latin, or philosophy, or calculus, history, literature, biology, etc. What I am suggesting is that the discovery of such benefits would require one to dig beneath the surface a bit. This sounds easy enough, not to mention quite logical; indeed, as Friedrich Nietzsche once wrote, “Honest things, like honest men, do not carry their reasons exposed in this fashion. It is indecent to display all one’s goods.”

And now we come to what I would contend is the true source of the problem: ours is a fast food culture.  Consider for a moment the tremendous success of books like The Idiot’s Guide to the Iliad or The Bible for Dummies or (my personal favorite) Heidegger in 90 Minutes. Consider the tremendous success of Wikipedia.  Indeed, why should we spend years of our lives laboring over works like the Iliad, the Bible, and Being and Time, when the fast-food versions of these highly sophisticated and highly difficult texts are readily available to us?  (I’m reminded as well of an infomercial I saw years ago during one of my many bouts with insomnia. The company that produced it was trying to sell a secret speed-reading technique, and the fellow flipping through various books in the manner of Good Will Hunting was held up as proof positive of the efficacy of this dazzling new technique. After all, he was quite capable of answering any and all questions raised by his trusty interlocutor. He swore that he hadn’t prepared answer to these questions in advance, so...

But that’s beside the point. My first thought upon seeing this was how much fun it would be to hand this speed-reader a copy of Heidegger’s Being and Time or Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, assuming that he himself actually believed in the product he was selling, and either watch him get stuck on the first page or wait until he had finished and then pose a question like “To what extent does Heidegger’s analysis of mood in Dasein inform and/or enhance his phenomenological hermeneutics of the question of the meaning of being?” 

My second thought was, why on earth would anyone want to read a book that quickly? Isn’t it precisely the process of reading that we voracious readers find so gratifying? Well, I suppose that if one reads books to impress potential love-interests at cocktail parties, or potential employers at job interviews, then speed-reading might be the way to go. Such contexts demand little more – indeed, allow for little more – than surface details. Believe you me, the fellow who wishes to delve into the ramifications of the antinomies in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is seldom (and by seldom I mean never) the life of the party. So why not invest in such manuals of popularity as The Iliad for Idiots or The Bible for Boneheads? Why not take that speed-reading course?

Well, one good reason, to return to the fast food metaphor, is that should we partake of such fare, we would thereby run the risk of bringing upon ourselves what one might call ‘intellectual indigestion,’ or, if you like, on the other end, ‘cognitive diarrhea.’

Now, I’m not trying to be slick or clever; I am in deadly earnest. The situation is dire. At stake are our very souls.

Yes, our souls. The fact that many if not most doubt the existence of souls is itself symptomatic of the problem I’m addressing. Though it should be noted that when I use the word ‘soul’ I do not intend it in the sense of a Christian immortal soul; I mean it more in the sense of the ancient Greek notion of that star stuff imbuing our bodies with life. But I digress… Well, I do and I don’t…

But what am I saying, in more concrete terms? A liberal arts education, as I understand it, is one that puts us in touch with the works of truly great human beings. And the driving force behind such an education is an endeavor to set the student free. I know how hokey and trite that sounds, but bear with me a moment. It used to be the case that one might pursue a liberal arts education – a true liberal arts education – at the college level, and this may even still be the case in certain isolated pockets of the country.  But those days are numbered.  hese days one goes to college to learn a trade, and the rare individual who does have aspirations of studying the “liberal arts” is more often than not halted before she’s started, halted by the omnipresent voice of our culture assuring her that utility is the be-all end-all, not just of education but of life itself. That voice doesn’t tell her to what end such utility is directed, but it speaks so vociferously and so interminably that it hardly matters. And the reason it refuses to speak of ends, this ubiquitous voice of our culture, is that it believes the whole notion of “ends” is obsolete and outmoded. There is no end save utility itself, which I scarcely need to tell you is, as an end, utterly and completely vacuous.  One might just as well assert that the end of life is living.

But that’s ok, because we educators still have an opportunity to reach them in secondary school. Right?  Well…  What I find truly frightening – and this not just as it pertains to my own job security – is the fact that this mad drive toward utility for utility’s sake has already begun infecting high schools. It used to be quite common for a student to arrive at college with very little notion of what major she wished to declare. Now, whenever such a student is bold enough to admit that she really doesn’t know what major she will declare, she is usually met with that knowing stare, the one that says, “Do you really think it’s alright to waste so much money on something so flighty as ‘finding yourself’?” And so that same student is frightened into a proper career, like engineering, or medicine, or law, and quite possibly looks back upon her life at the age of forty-five or fifty and wonders what the hell it’s all been for.

We need the liberal arts, in all their glorious uselessness, because they provide the only means of freeing ourselves from the ever-present banality of our culture, a banality that signals the very real threat that one day – perhaps sooner, perhaps later – convention will swallow every last one of us. And that will be the day when the light of our souls is extinguished once and for all.

I’d like to end with one of my favorite quotations. At the beginning of his book called An Introduction to Metaphysics, Martin Heidegger speaks precisely of the questionable utility of philosophy, but I would suggest that what he says of philosophy applies equally well to Latin, and history, and art; in short, all those useless subjects with which we engage in high school.  He writes:

“It is absolutely correct and proper to say that ‘You can’t do anything with philosophy’. It is only wrong to suppose that this is the last word on philosophy. For the rejoinder imposes itself: Granted that we cannot do anything with philosophy, might not philosophy, if we concern ourselves with it, do something with us?”

Monday, January 16, 2012

Salvete, Omnes!

This is the very first of what I hope will become an indefinite series of weekly posts.  The aim is to share with all interested parties any and all news pertaining specifically to the study of Latin at WRA.  This will hopefully include updates on all of the good work the Latin Club has done.  If I have forgotten to mention something that you believe to be relevant and/or significant, please don't hesitate to let me know.  Although I am myself quite new to the world of blogging, I suspect that the best blogs are dynamic and open to change.

I'm very happy to report that as of this first post Latin is alive and well at Western Reserve Academy.  We have two sizable sections of Latin I, two sections of Latin II, a section of Latin III, and a section of Latin III Honors.  This latter is a new course, which was designed as a more rigorous version of Latin II Honors and ultimately better suited for preparing students for AP Latin the following year.  Since this is the course's pilot year, as it were, its stands to reason that we put AP Latin on hold until next year.  (And, after teaching Vergil consecutively for the past eleven years, I miss him even more that I thought I would!)

The Latin Club is currently in the initial stages of putting together a presentation for WRA's "Culture Night," which will take place this year on February 12th.  In addition, they will work with me to whip up some genuine ancient Roman cuisine for the gustatory delectation of all attendees.  (I should perhaps make the following qualification: while all of the recipes derive from the ancient Roman cookbook of Alpicius, there are certain items for which we really do not have the stomachs, e.g., fried dormice, garum, i.e., liquified fish guts, etc.  With all such items, creative substitutions are utilized.)  The larger, year-long project for the Latin Club is the development of a "Classics Day" right here at WRA.  We envision setting aside a day for the celebration of all things Greco-Roman, with certamina (intellectual combat), a costume contest, a brief lecture from a guest lecturer, a chariot race, a "toga-run," and more.  We'd like to invite students and teachers from many of the local schools, including Hudson High School, University School, etc.  Stay tuned for further updates on this truly exciting project as the year progresses.

Finally, we're just fifty-four days away from departure for Italy and Greece.  Over Spring Break I'll be supervising a tour to Italy and Greece through a company called EF Tours.  The name of the tour is "From Rome to Athens," and as you might well imagine, we'll visit many places in between.  My personal favorites are Rome, Pompeii, Mycenae, Athens, & Delphi, but we'll see a number of other places as well, including the Greek Isles!  For reasons that are perhaps obvious, I'm especially eager for the latter.

Well, thanks for reading, and I hope you'll return regularly!

Si valetis, valeo!

Mr. Namiotka